• Tidak ada hasil yang ditemukan

View of GENERAL POLYNOMIAL MATH, TOPOLOGICAL POLYNOMIAL MATH: TOPOLOGICAL ALGEBRAS

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2023

Membagikan "View of GENERAL POLYNOMIAL MATH, TOPOLOGICAL POLYNOMIAL MATH: TOPOLOGICAL ALGEBRAS"

Copied!
4
0
0

Teks penuh

(1)

VOLUME: 07, Special Issue 08, Paper id-IJIERM-VII-VIII, December 2020

83

GENERAL POLYNOMIAL MATH, TOPOLOGICAL POLYNOMIAL MATH: TOPOLOGICAL ALGEBRAS

Dr. H. K. Tripathi

Lecturer, Govt. Women’s Polytechnic College, Jabalpur-482001

Abstract- As well as investigating developments and properties of cutoff points and co cutoff points in classifications of topological algebras, we study unique subcategories of topological algebras and their properties. Specifically, under specific conditions, responsive subcategories when combined with topological designs lead to reective subcategories and epireective subcategories bring about epireective subcategories.

Keywords: Monotopolocial class, topological classification, topological functors, general polynomial math, topological polynomial math, reective subcategory, coreective subcategory, epireective subcategory.

1 INTRODUCTION

Basically a topological polynomial math is a general variable based math blessed with a topological design so mathematical activities are consistent in all factors together. Wyler has summed up the development of classes of topological algebras (see [15]), by getting from what he calls a \top" class (which is identical to the idea topological classification) Cs and a functional classification an over a class C another class Ar which is \top" over and functional over Cs, with a pullback property. Fay further summed up the classes of topological algebras utilizing an idea called topologically mathematical circumstance (see [4]). Later Nel ([11]) and Koslowski ([9]) have given depictions that are embraced in our work. To begin with, let us depict a few ideas utilized in this work.

2 PRELIMINARIES

There are a few definitions for the term \algebraic functor" in the writing, which are all identical in some uncommon classes, yet not overall. We decide to receive the accompanying famous definition [8, page 243]. A functor is called logarithmic U has a left ad joint and jelly and reects customary epimorphisms.

(2)

VOLUME: 07, Special Issue 08, Paper id-IJIERM-VII-VIII, December 2020

84

Commutes. A functor is said to be essentially algebraic [6] provided that it creates isomorphisms and is (generating, monosource) - factorizable. If

is an essentially algebraic functor and faithfull, then (X;U) is called an essentially algebraic category over Y .

A functor is called uniquely transportable i any X-isomorphism can be lifted via U to a unique A-isomorphism . For a later use, we will formulate a result in the following Theorem, whose proof can be found in [1, 23.2].

Theorem 2.1

The accompanying conditions are identical for an extraordinarily movable (producing, monosource) - factorizable functor .

(a) U is basically logarithmic.

(b) U reflects isomorphisms.

(c) U reects limits.

(d) U reflects equalizers.

(e) U reflects extremal epimorphisms and is unwavering.

(f) Every mono source in X is U-beginning. called an Ω-algebra (see, for example, [3]).

For the sake of simplicity, we write A instead of the pair and for the nj-ary operation nj on A. If the Ω-algebra A is clear from the context, we drop the sux A in denoting its nj-ary operation. If A and B are Ω-algebras, then a mapping

is said to be an Ω-morphism is

the mapping with the obvious definition The symbol Alg(Ω) denotes the category whose objects are Ω-algebras and whose morphisms are Ω- morphisms. Alg(Ω) is algebraic over Set (see [1, 7.72 (3), 23.6 (1), 23E (a)]).

A subcategory of an algebraic category, in general, may not be algebraic. However, this is guaranteed by several equivalent conditions for a special type of subcategory. To state this result we need the de_nition of an isomorphism closed subcategory. A subcategory A of B is called isomorphism closed i every isomorphism in B whose domain or co domain belongs to A is a morphism in A. We state two results in this direction whose proofs can be found in the stated references.

Theorem 2.2 On the off chance that (B, U) is a logarithmic class and A will be a full isomorphism shut subcategory of B with installing to such an extent that An is shut under the arrangement of sub objects in B, then, at that point coming up next are comparable [8, 38.2]:

(a) is mathematical.

(b) An is reflective in B.

(c) A will be a finished subcategory of B.

(d) An is shut under the development of items in B.

Hypothesis 1.3 An isomorphism shut full subcategory An of Alg(ω) is epireective in Alg(ω) i An is shut under the arrangement of items and sub algebras ([7], [1, 20.18, 23.6(1), 23.12(1), 16.9]). Presently we can finish up, as an outcome of these two outcomes, that a full isomorphism shut epireective subcategory An of Alg(ω) is logarithmic over Set and consequently concedes free Ω-algebras and has customary factorizations in light of the fact that arithmetical class over Set means routinely mathematical classification over Set in the feeling of [1, 23.35,23.38, 23.39]. A full isomorphism shut epireective subcategory of Alg(ω) is generally alluded to as a SP-class or as a quasiprimitive classification of algebras. A full subcategory An of the class Alg(ω) is an assortment (in the feeling of [3]) I An is shut under sub algebras, homomorphic pictures and direct items. An assortment is likewise called a HSP-class or a crude classification of algebras. An assortment is an epireective subcategory of Alg(ω) (by Theorem 3) and is arithmetical over Set (by Theorem 2). In this way every

(3)

VOLUME: 07, Special Issue 08, Paper id-IJIERM-VII-VIII, December 2020

85

nontrivial assortment has free algebras. Since each mathematical develop is topologically logarithmic, both SP-classes and HSP-classes are topologically arithmetical over Set. The accompanying hypothesis, whose verification can be found in [1, 23.8, 23.13], reveals some insight on basically arithmetical subcategories of Alg(ω).

3 PAIRED CATEGORIES

Let X be a construct withnite concrete powers and A be a subcategory of Alg (Ω). By a paired object (from X and A) is meant an ordered pair (X, A) where X and A are objects in X and A respectively with the same underlying set such that, for each , the n(= nj)-ary operation on A is an X-morphism . In this case, we write for the X-morphism from Xn to X whose underlying function is and (X′, A′) are two paired objects (from X and A), then an X-morphism that is also an A- morphism is called a paired morphism (from X and A) and is denoted by

. The category of all paired objects (from X and A) together with paired morphisms (from X and A) is called the paired category (from X and A). We denote this category by .

4 SUBCATEGORIES

Let us first discuss the construction of subcategories of from subcategories of X and of A. It is clear that if B is a subcategory of A, then is a subcategory of . On the other hand, if Y is a subcategory of X then the category need not be a subcategory of because concrete powers in Y need not agree with the concrete powers in X. Here is an example:

Example 4.1 The additive group IR of real numbers with its usual topology, i.e., with the nearness structure

constitutes a counterexample since IR is a topological group but not a nearness group:

The addition is not uniformly continuous with respect to the Near product structure on (for a detailed proof, see [2]). However, we have the following result.

Theorem 4.2 If Y is a subcategory of X such that concrete powers in Y agree with concrete powers in X then is a subcategory of . In particular, if Y is an epireective subcategory of X, then is a subcategory of .

Proof. Let be any object in For each the nj-th product Y nj of Y in the category Y is the same as the nj-th product of Y in the category X and the nj-ary operation being a morphism in Y , must be a morphism in X. Thus (Y;A) is also an object. Obviously -morphisms are also morphisms in .

If Y is an epireective subcategory of X, then the products in Y do agree with those in X so that YA is a subcategory of XA by what was proved above.

However, we have the following result.

(4)

VOLUME: 07, Special Issue 08, Paper id-IJIERM-VII-VIII, December 2020

86

Theorem 4.2 If Y is a subcategory of X such that concrete powers in Y agree with concrete powers in X then is a subcategory of .

In particular, if Y is an epireective subcategory of X, then Y

A is a subcategory of .

Proof. Let (Y, A) be any object in . For each j 2 J, the nj-th product Y nj of Y in the category Y is the same as the nj-th product of Y in the category X and the nj-ary operation being a morphism in Y , must be a morphism in X. Thus (Y, A) is also an -object. Obviously -morphisms are also morphisms in XA. If Y is an epireective subcategory of X, then the products in Y do agree with those in X so that is a subcategory of by what was proved above.

If Y is a coreective subcategory of X, then any object in is also in if its first part is already in Y . In other words:

Theorem 4.3 If Y is a coreective subcategory of X and the pair (X;A) is an object in X

A such that X is an object in Y then (X;A) is also an object in .

Proof. We need to prove that each algebraic operation on A is a Y -morphism. Let and To avoid ambiguity, let us use the symbol Y to indicate X regarded as a-object and write Y n and Xn for the products of X to itself n times in the categories Y and X respectively. Since Y is coreective in X, the Y -product Y n is the Y –coreection of the X- product Xn. Therefore, any X-morphism is also a Y -morphism

. In particular, the nj-ary operation on A being an X-morphism is indeed a Y -morphism

5 LIMITS AND CO LIMITS

In, Wyler shows, in addition to other things, that assuming X is a topological classification, every single clear cut breaking point and co cutoff points can be lifted from a classification An of algebras to the classification X⋄A. Specifically, in case X is a topological classification and An is finished and co complete then X⋄A is finished and co complete. Since each mono topological classification is an epireective subcategory of a topological classification, comparative outcomes are valid in case X is a mono topological classification. In this segment we expect to portray a few cutoff points and co cutoff points in the combined classification X⋄A under the suspicion that X is mono topological. We start with a Theorem that is exceptionally valuable in our work.

REFERENCES

1. J. Adamek, H. Herrlich and G. E. Strecker, Abstract and Concrete Categories, John Wiley & Sons, Inc., New York, 1990.

2. H. L. Bentley, H. Herrlich and R. G. Ori, Zero sets and completes regularity for nearness spaces, In:

Categorical Topology, World Scienti c, Teaneck, New Jersey (1989), 446-461.

3. P. M. Cohn, Universal Algebra, Harper and Row, Publishers, New York, 1965

4. T. H. Fay, An axiomatic approach to categories of topological algebras, Quaestiones Mathematician 2 (1977), 113-137.

5. V. L. Gompa, Essentially algebraic functors and topological algebra, Indian Journal of Mathematics, 35, (1993), 189-195.

6. H. Herrlich, Essentially algebraic categories, Quaest. Math. 9 (1986), 245-262

7. Y. H. Hong, Studies on categories of universal topological algebras, Doctoral Dissertation, McMaster University, 1974.

8. H. Herrlich and G. E. Strecker, Category Theory, Allyn and Bacon, Boston, 1973

9. J. Koslowski, Dual adjunctions and the compatibility of structures, In: Categorical Topology, Heldermann Verlag, Berlin (1984), 308-322.

10. J. D. Lawson and B. L. Madison, On congruences and cones, Math. Zeit. 120 (1971), 18-24.

Referensi

Dokumen terkait

รูปแบบการจัดการเรียนรู้เชิงรุกโดยใช้ปัญหาเป็นฐาน เพือส่งเสริมสมรรถนะนักศึกษาการศึกษานอกระบบและการศึกษาตามอัธยาศัย Problem-Based Active Learning Model on Non-formal Education