• Tidak ada hasil yang ditemukan

Directory UMM :Data Elmu:jurnal:M:Mathematical Social Sciences:Vol40.Issue1.Jul2000:

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2017

Membagikan "Directory UMM :Data Elmu:jurnal:M:Mathematical Social Sciences:Vol40.Issue1.Jul2000:"

Copied!
22
0
0

Teks penuh

(1)

www.elsevier.nl / locate / econbase

Consistent aggregation of simply scalable families of choice

probabilities

a ,* b b c

´ ´ ´

Janos Aczel , Attila Gilanyi , Gyula Maksa , Anthony A.J. Marley

a

Faculty of Mathematics, University of Waterloo, Waterloo, Ontario N2L 3G1, Canada

b

Institute of Mathematics and Informatics, Lajos Kossuth University, H-4010 Debrecen, Hungary

c

´ ´

Department of Psychology, McGill University, Montreal, Quebec H3A 1B1, Canada

Received 31 May 1998; received in revised form 30 November 1998; accepted 31 March 1999

Abstract

We characterize probabilistic choice models that have two (or more) fixed ratio scales associated with each choice option. A version of Luce’s choice model with fixed scales and exponents, which we also characterize, is included. The characterizing properties are: Simple scalability, i.e. the choice probabilities depend upon a priori arbitrary combinations of the two scale values attached to each choice option. Aggregation equations express that both the probabilities and the scales are aggregated from individual to overall values. Generalized homogeneity type equations appear because we deal with ratio scales. As regards regularity, we suppose only local boundedness, non-constancy and an injectivity condition.  2000 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Aggregation; Scales; Choice probabilities; Choice models; Functional equations

1. Introduction

´ ´

Aczel, Maksa, Marley and Moszner (Aczel et al., 1997) characterized Luce’s choice model and a considerably more general class of choice models by scaling and aggregation properties. The representations studied there were ‘uni-dimensional’ in that each object of choice was assumed to be evaluated in terms of a single (ratio scale)

´

value. (These were called in (Aczel et al., 1997) ‘selection models’ to emphasize that the objects of choice could be sets; this interpretation is implicitly permitted also here, for our ‘choice models’ and ‘choice probabilities’). In this paper we generalize those results to ‘two-dimensional’ (‘multi-dimensional’) representations. Without our aggregation

*Corresponding author. Tel.:11-519-866-6156; fax:11-519-725-0106. ´

E-mail address: jdaczel@math.uwaterloo.ca (J. Aczel)

(2)

conditions, our representation for choice between two-dimensional objects would be similar to that of (Falmagne and Iverson, 1979) (Theorems 7 and 8), which deals with the binary (n52) case. The assumptions were different in (Falmagne and Iverson, 1979), which also contains more general models, with the relation to Luce’s choice model less visible. We use one of their motivating examples to illustrate our approach: Consider an experiment in which a person hears a sequence of pure tone bursts which are all of the same frequency but of different intensities and durations, and the person has to decide which burst is the loudest. For instance, if each pure tone sequence consisted of 3 bursts, the person could indicate which burst was ‘loudest’ by saying ‘first’ or ‘second’ or ‘third’, referring thereby to the relevant component. Assume that there are scales v, w such that each tone burst d can be specified by the two

(nonnegative) scale values v(d ), w(d ); for instance, v(d ) might measure the tone’s

psychological intensity (‘loudness’), and w(d ) the tone’s psychological (perceived) duration. (Of course, the intensity and duration of two different tone bursts may occasionally be perceived the same). Since such comparisons are frequently ‘noisy’, let

P(e:E ) denote the probability that tone burst e is judged the loudest in the set E. A

special case of the representation that we derive in this paper has the following form: there are non-zero constants a,b such that

a b v(e) w(e)

]]]]

P(e:E )5

O

a b. (1)

v(d ) w(d ) d[E

We will call a choice model with (1) as choice probability by the inelegant but descriptive name ‘two-scale Luce model with exponents’ (for the ‘original’ Luce model

´

cf. (Aczel et al., 1997) and (13)). Going one step further, in order to introduce our aggregation ideas, now suppose that we have data from m subjects for each of whom the choice probability satisfies (1), but with different scales. That is, P (e:E ), the probabilityi

that tone burst e is ‘chosen’ as the loudest in the set E by subject i, is of the form given in (1) with different scalesv, w (i51, . . . ,m). Now suppose that we wish to create a

i i

representation of the performance of an ‘average’ person in this task, perhaps for use in a clinical setting for deciding whether a particular person is performing better or worse than one might expect ‘on average’. What form should we assume for the (probabilistic) performance of this ‘average’ person? Given that each individual satisfies (1), it seems reasonable to assume a parallel representation for the ‘average’ person. In particular, consider the case where the ‘aggregate’ (average) choice probability P(e:E ) is of the form (1) with scale values given, for each d in E, by

m

m m

ci ci

v(d )5

P

v(d ) , w(d )5

P

w (d )

S

O

c 5c±0 .

D

(2)

i i i

i51 i51 i51

m

(3)

values and thus the choice probabilities in (1) are nonzero. This we will suppose also for other choice probabilities.

The question seems interesting whether the choice probabilities of this ‘average’ person can be ‘aggregated’ from the choice probabilities of the m individual subjects. To be exact, our question (which we answer affirmatively) is: can this ‘aggregate’ choice probability P(e:E ) also be written as an ‘aggregate’ of the component choice prob-abilities P (e:E ) (ii 51, . . . ,m). We can do this by choosing the aggregating formula for the P’s as

m

ci

P

P (e:E )i i51

]]]]]

P(e:E )5 m . (3)

ci

OP

P (d:E )i

i51

d[E

Indeed we get from (1) and (2)

m

c ai c bi

P

v(e) w (e)

i i i51

]]]]]]

P(e:E )5 m .

c ai c bi

OP

v(d ) w (d )

i i i51

d[E

On the other hand, by formulas similar to (1) but for P ,i

c a b

m v i

(e) w (e)

f

i i

g

m

P

]]]]]]]c m

i a b

ci i51

O

v(d9) w (d9) c ai c bi

P

P (e:E )

F

i i

G

P

v(e) w (e)

i i i

i51 d9[E i51

]]]]]m 5]]]]]]]]]m v a b ci 5]]]]]]m .

(d ) w (d )

f

g

ci i i c ai c bi

OP

P (d:E )

OP

]]]]]]]

OP

v(d ) w (d )

i a b ci i i

i51 i51

d[E d[Ei51

O

v(d9) w (d9) d[E i i

F

d9[E

G

Thus we have (3).

So this ‘aggregation’ rule is plausible in that it ‘works’ both at the level of the choice probabilities and at the level of the scale values. A major contribution of this paper is to study ‘natural’ conditions under which the above result holds, and to consider generalizations to other choice probabilities besides (1).

It is interesting to observe that we can define new ‘scales’ for each option e in E, with

aAi1bBi5c (ii 51, . . . ,m), by

m m

Ai Bi

˜ ˜

v(e:E )5

P

P (e:E ) , w(e:E )5

P

P (e:E ) . (4)

i i

i51 i51

Then, by (3),

a b

˜ ˜

v(e:E ) w(e:E )

]]]]]]

P(e:E )5 a b,

˜ ˜

O

v(d:E ) w(d:E ) d[E
(4)

˜ ˜

terms of ‘scales’ v, w that are functions of the component choice probabilities P (e:E ) i

(i51, . . . ,m).

In the above example, we assumed that we had data from m individuals, which we wanted to ‘aggregate’ in some sensible fashion. We now briefly present an example where it might be plausible to assume that all the data are from a single person, and that the ‘aggregation’ is carried out by the person (either consciously or unconsciously). In a

complete identification task, there is a (finite) set of stimuli E, and each f[E is assigned

a unique ‘correct’ response r[ f ]. On each trial of the experiment, the participant’s task is to attempt to ‘correctly’ identify a presented stimulus f[E by making the response r[ f ]. Then paralleling (1), the probability P(r[e]uf :E ) (e, f[F ) is interpreted as the

probability that an option (stimulus) f[E is identified as the option (stimulus) e[E,

i.e., that the response r[e] is made to the stimulus f. In a similarity choice model or biased Luce model (Luce, 1963; Townsend and Landon, 1982) these probabilities are of the form

h( f,e)b(r[e]) ]]]]]

P(r[e]uf :E )5

O

(5)

h( f,d )b(r[d])

d[E

(often the notation P (r[e]E u f ) is used), with the constraints

0#h( f,e)#1, h( f,e)5h(e, f ), h(e,e)51,

0#b(r[e])#1,

O

b(r[d])51. (6)

d[E

The usual interpretation is thath is the stimulus scale or similarity scale and b the response scale or bias scale (it is usually denoted by b). We see that, for each fixed f and for given scaleshandb, P(r[e]u f :E ) is a two-scale Luce choice probability (that is, a

two-scale Luce choice probability with exponents a5b51) — at least within the bounds usually imposed upon values of the scalesh and b. (Our mathematical results apply also if the scales forh and b are assumed to be ratio scales even for very large scale values. The issue of fitting our results to the usual formulation of similarity choice models will be considered in Section 5). A natural generalization of this representation to the multi-component case involves m similarity and bias functions hi,bi (i5 1, . . . ,m), where each i is associated with a different ‘component’ of the options — for instance, the (visual) objects being categorized may differ on the ‘independent’ dimensions of size, shape, and color ((Marley, 1992) discusses in detail the complexities caused by the fact that even though these dimensions can be varied ‘independently’, each such visual object must have a value on each of these dimensions). The various concepts and results developed for the previous example then apply naturally for this example. Of course, as in the first example, the similarity scaleshi and the bias scalebi

(i51, . . . ,m) may not depend on the components i (i51, . . . ,m), but deciding whether this is the case or not is an empirical and statistical issue. In fact, there are quite complex issues related to fitting two-scale Luce choice probabilities, their aggregates, and our later more general representations, to empirical data (see Remark 7 below); (Ashby et al., 1994) is an excellent introduction to these issues for the similarity choice model.

(5)

m individuals or for a single individual on m different occasions (rather than across m

dimensions for a single individual) and consider appropriate ways to ‘aggregate’ this data. Our earlier discussion illustrated our results concerning the ‘correct’ way to perform such aggregation when one wishes the component and the aggregate forms to be related in certain systematic ways.

In summary, we have illustrated representations that can be aggregated both at the level of the scalesv, w (orh,b) and at the level of the component choice probabilities

i i i i

P (ii 51, . . . ,m). In this paper we characterize the class of scale-dependent probabilistic models for choice between ‘two-dimensional’ options that have similar aggregation properties, where the forms of the aggregation and probabilistic choice functions are

derived, rather than assumed as they have been in the above examples.

We now discuss the relevance of the introductory examples to the remainder of the paper and the relation of the paper to earlier work. Let E5he , . . . ,e1 nj, souEu5n. If we

define functions h, K and F ( jj 51, . . . ,n) on the positive reals by

a b

h(x, y)5x y , (7)

zj

]]

K (z , . . . ,z )j 1 n 5 n ( j51, . . . ,n), (8)

O

zk k51

a b x yj j

]]]

F (x , y , . . . ,x , y )j 1 1 n n 5 n ( j51, . . . ,n) (9)

a b

O

x yk k k51

then (1) in the earlier example takes the form

P(e :E )5F [v(e ),w(e ), . . . ,v(e ),w(e )]

j j 1 1 n n

5K [h(v(e ),w(e )), . . . ,h(v(e ),w(e ))] ( j51, . . . ,n). (10)

j 1 1 n n

´ Eq. (8) is of the form of the expression for the ‘original’ Luce choice model (see (Aczel et al., 1997) and (13) below).

Notice the following properties (i), (ii), (iii) of these functions, with terminology for properties (i) and (ii) generalized from their n52 form in (Falmagne and Iverson, 1979) ((ii) further generalized from (10) to allow n functions h , . . . ,h which, as we1 n

will later prove, have to be equal). These equations are meant for arbitrary m,n,l,x , y ,zj j j.0 ( j51, . . . ,n), though smaller intervals would do.

• (i) ‘Conjoint Weber Type II’:

F (j mx ,1ny , . . . ,1 mx ,nny )n 5F (x , y , . . . ,x , y ) ( jj 1 1 n n 51, . . . ,n);

• (ii) ‘Simple Scalability’:

F (x , y , . . . ,x , y )j 1 1 n n 5K (h (x , y ), . . . ,h (x , y )) ( jj 1 1 1 n n n 51, . . . ,n);

(6)

K (j lz , . . . ,1 lz )n 5K (z , . . . ,z ) ( jj 1 n 51, . . . ,n).

The homogeneity (iii) looks similar to (i) and will turn out to be related to it through (ii).

In this paper we develop aggregation conditions which, with (i), (ii), (iii) and under some simple regularity conditions, imply a choice model which includes (1) as particular case. Then we give conditions which characterize just (1). This characterization will also show why powers and not other functions figure in (1). This is related to consideringv

and w as ratio scales.

2. Definitions, assumptions, equations

We will call choice probability and denote by P(e:E ) the probability of choosing (selecting) an element (option) e from an n-element (1,n, `) subset E of a global set

R of options. We exclude elements which are impossible to choose. Thus,

0,P(e:E ),1 (11)

and, of course,

O

P(e:E )51. (12)

e[E

We now formally define this and further concepts required in this paper (interspersed with remarks).

Definition 1. Let R be a set and S the set of its finite subsets, where both R and every E[S has at least two elements, and D5h(e:E )uE[S, e[Ej7R3S. The pair (R, P)

consisting of the set R and of the function P: D]0,1[is a choice model. The function value P(e:E ) (e[E, E[S ) is a choice probability, e is an option.

Remark 1. While here we required that R have at least two elements, a later assumption

will imply that it has uncountably infinite elements (see Definition 3, Remark 4).

Definition 2. A choice model, two functionsv, w: R→ ]0,`[ and two nonzero numbers a, b form a two-scale Luce model with exponents if (1), that is

a b v(e) w(e)

]]]]

P(e:E )5

O

a b

v(d ) w(d ) d[E

holds. If a5b51 then we have a two-scale Luce model. The functionsvand w are the scales, v(e), w(e) are scale values.

Remark 2. Here and throughout the paper the scalesv and w are given; otherwise not

(7)

a b

by a single scale u5v w and we would have the original (one-scale) Luce model (cf.

´

(Aczel et al., 1997) and (8))

u(e)

]]]

P(e:E )5

O

. (13)

u(d ) d[E

Notice, however, that, if the choice probabilities can be represented in the form (1) with scales v, w, they can equally well be represented by scales gv, dw with arbitrary

constantsg .0,d .0.

As we said in the Introduction, our purpose in this paper is to determine those scale-dependent (two-scale, see Definition 4) families of choice probabilities for which formulae like (10)

P(e : E )5F [v(e ),w(e ), . . . ,v(e ),w(e )]

j j 1 1 n n

5K [h (v(e ),w(e )), . . . ,h (v(e ),w(e ))] ( j51, . . . ,n) (14) j 1 1 1 n n n

hold, where both the scales and the probabilities can be aggregated. This means that, in analogy to (2) and (3), equations of the form

v(e )5G

f

v (e ), . . . ,v (e ) , w(e )

g

5G w (e ), . . . ,w (e ) ,

f

g

j 1 1 j m j j 2 1 j m j P(e : E )j 5H P (e : E ), . . . ,P (e : E ), . . . ,P (e : E ), . . . ,P (e : E ) ,jf 1 1 m 1 1 n m n g

( j51, . . . ,n) are satisfied, where the component probabilities satisfy equations analo-gous to (14) with the same F ( jj 51, . . . ,n):

P (e : E )5F [v(e ),w (e ), . . . ,v(e ),w (e )] i j j i 1 i 1 i n i n

5K [h (v(e ),w (e )), . . . ,h (v(e ),w (e ))] j 1 i 1 i 1 n i n i n

(i51, . . . ,m; j51, . . . ,n). (15)

These equations, with assumptions linked to v, w and their combinations h (v, w )

i i j i i

being ratio scales, will lead to functional equations, from which we will endeavor to determine the functions h , K (and thus F ; jj j j 51, . . . ,n) obtaining in passing also the general forms of G ,G and, under further restrictions, H ( j1 2 j 51, . . . ,n). The variables in these equations will go through the setR of positive numbers, because we will deal

11

with nonatomic scales (in analogy to nonatomic Kolmogorov probability spaces, see e.g. ´

in (Renyi, 1970)). These are such that the scales can assume any positive value. (We will make further assumptions in Definitions 3 and 4).

A nonatomic pair of scales is a triple (R,v, w), where R is a set andv, w: R→R 11

2

are scales (functions) such that for every pair (x, y)[R there exists an e[R for

11

which x5v(e), y5w(e).

Remark 3. Nonatomicity has the following consequence. For each (2n)-tuple

2n

(x , y , . . . ,x , y )[R for which (x , y )±(x , y ) if j±k (that is, the same (x , y )

1 1 n n 11 j j k k j j

n

pair does not occur more than once) there exist (e , . . . ,e )[R such that x 5v(e ),

(8)

yj5w(e ) ( jj 51, . . . ,n). The bold exclusion was necessary because otherwise E may not have n distinct elements; in particular it may have just one element — but we

´

excluded singletons (cf. (11)). Therefore we will need here (as in (Aczel et al., 1997)) a somewhat stronger condition, the n-nonatomicity which postulates the existence of different (distinct) elements e ±e even if x 5x , y 5y thus v(e )5x 5x 5v(e ), j k j k j k j j k k w(e )j 5yj5yk5w(e ) ( jk ±k). This is not unexpected: For instance, e ,e might be twoj k

different cars that a person considers equal in safety (x 5v(e )5v(e )5x ) and equal j j k k

in road handling (second dimension yj5w(e )j 5w(e )k 5y ); see also the example in thek

Introduction about equal perceived intensity and duration for different tone bursts.

We define now the n-nonatomicity formally.

Definition 3. An n-nonatomic pair of scales is a quadruple (R,v, w, n), where R is a set, v, w: R→R are scales (functions) and n.1 is an integer such that for every

11

(2n)-tuple (x , y , . . . ,x , y ) of positive numbers there exist n distinct elements e , . . . ,e1 1 n n 1 n

of R for which x 5v(e ), y 5w(e ) ( j51, . . . ,n). j j j j

Remark 4. While the n-nonatomicity assumption clearly implies that the global set R is

uncountably infinite, the choice is always done from finite subsets E of R (as is appropriate for applications in psychology and elsewhere). The papers (Falmagne, 1981; Marley, 1982) discuss the use (and misuse) of nonatomicity in related problems without explicitly defining this concept.

Remark 5. Of course, there may exist not only ej±e of the same set E with equalk

scale values but to a 2n-tuple of positive reals there may also exist two (or more)

n 2n

9 9

n-tuple(s) (e , . . . ,e ), (e , . . . ,e ) in R such that, for the same (x , y , . . . ,x , y )[R

1 n 1 n 1 1 n n 11

9 9

simultaneously x 5v(e )5v(e ), y 5w(e )5w(e ) ( j51, . . . ,n) hold. The last part of

j j j j j j

the next definition refers to this situation.

Definition 4. Let n.1 be an integer. An n-nonatomic two-scale family of choice

probabilities (a two-scale model for short) is a 5-tuple (R, P,v, w, n), where (R, P) is a

choice model with only n element subsets E of R considered and (R, v, w, n) is an n-nonatomic pair of scales such that, whenever for two subsets E5he , . . . ,e1 nj and

9 9 9 9

E9 5he , . . . ,e j of R we have v(e )5v(e ) and w(e )5w(e ) ( j51, . . . ,n) then also

1 n j j j j

9

P(e :E )j 5P(e :Ej 9) ( j51, . . . ,n).

Remark 6. The last requirement, where n has an essential role, implies that there exist

2n

functions F :R →]0,1[ such that

j 11

P(e : E )5F (v(e ),w(e ), . . . ,v(e ),w(e )) ( j51, . . . ,n)

j j 1 1 n n

(9)

probability P. As already mentioned, we will suppose that P and P (ii 51, . . . ,m) have the same generating system.

´ We generalize (1), (2) and (3) to the following aggregation equations (cf. (Aczel et al., 1997)):

P(e :E )5Ffv(e ),w(e ), . . . ,v(e ),w(e ) ,g (16)

j j 1 1 n n

P (e :E )5Ffv(e ),w (e ), . . . ,v(e ),w (e ) ,g (17) i j j i 1 i 1 i n i n

v(e )5G

f

v (e ), . . . ,v (e ) , w(e )

g

5G w (e ), . . . ,w (e ) ,

f

g

(18) j 1 1 j m j j 2 1 j m j

P(e :E )j 5H P (e :E ), . . . ,P (e :E ), . . . ,P (e :E ), . . . ,P (e :E ) ,jf 1 1 m 1 1 n m n g (19) here i51, . . . ,m and j51, . . . ,n. Substituting (18) into (16) on one hand and (17) into (19) on the other gives, in view of the nonatomicity, a system of n functional equations. The fact that the scales and the probabilities depending on them by (16) and (17) are invariant (covariant) under linear transformations (ratio scales) give 2n12 others. Finally (11) and (12) generate one more equation and n inequalities.

´

As in (Aczel et al., 1997), however, there would be far too many solutions for practical use and this system is far too weak to characterize the ‘‘two-scale Luce model with exponents’’ or even halfway reasonable generalizations. So two further spe-cifications are needed. The first links H more closely to F , at the same time introducingj j

two more scale values depending on the choice probabilities:

˜

v(e :E )5F[P (e :E ), . . . ,P (e :E )], j 1 1 j m j ˜

w(e :E )j 5F2[P (e :E ), . . . ,P (e :E )] ( j1 j m j 51, . . . ,n), (20) ´

(cf. (4) and (Aczel et al., 1997)) to which (16) should also apply:

˜ ˜ ˜ ˜

P(e :E )5F [v(e :E ),w(e :E ), . . . ,v(e :E ),w(e :E )] ( j51, . . . ,n) (21)

j j 1 1 n n

(the more specific Eq. (21) with (20) will replace (19)). The second (‘simple scalability’ (ii)) we know already (see (14)). We repeat it here to point out that it establishes a link between the two original sets of scales within F :j

P(e :E )5F [v(e ),w(e ), . . . ,v(e ),w(e )]

j j 1 1 n n

5K (h [v(e ),w(e )], . . . ,h [v(e ),w(e )]) ( j51, . . . ,n). (22) j 1 1 1 n n n

We list now the assumptions linked to v, w and the combinations h (v,w) of v and w

i i j

being ratio scales (i51, . . . ,m; j51, . . . ,n). There exist functions M , M such that1 2

G [gv (e ), . . . ,g v (e )]5M (g , . . . ,g )G [v(e ), . . . ,v (e )], (23)

1 1 1 1 m m m 1 1 m 1 1 1 m m

(10)

F [mv(e ),nw(e ), . . . ,mv(e ),nw(e )]5F [v(e ),w(e ), . . . ,v(e ),w(e )]

j 1 1 n n j 1 1 n n

( j51, . . . ,n),

(‘conjoint Weber type II’ (Falmagne and Iverson, 1979)), which translates for K and hj j

into

K (h [mv(e ),nw(e )], . . . ,h [mv(e ),nw(e )])

j 1 1 1 n n n

5K (h [v(e ),w(e )], . . . ,h [v(e ),w(e )]) ( j51, . . . ,n). (25) j 1 1 1 n n n

Furthermore there exists a function N such that

K (lh [v(e ),w(e )], . . . ,lh [v(e ),w(e )]) j 1 1 1 n n n

5N(l)K (h [v(e ),w(e )], . . . ,h [v(e ),w(e )]) ( j51, . . . ,n). (26) j 1 1 1 n n n

holds. Finally, the obvious equation (12) and inequalities (11) translate, in view of (16), into

n

O

F [v(e ),w(e ), . . . ,v(e ),w(e )]51, (27)

j 1 1 n n

j51

0,F [v(e ),w(e ), . . . ,v(e ),w(e )],1 ( j51, . . . ,n). (28)

j 1 1 n n

We introduce, for the sake of brevity, the notation (permitted by the n-nonatomicity)

x 5v(e ), y 5w(e ), z 5h (x , y ), j j j j j j j j

x 5v(e ), y 5w (e ) (i51, . . . ,m; j51, . . . ,n). (29) ij i j ij i j

(The scale values and thus these variables are supposed to be positive). So, by (22, 27–29),

n

O

K (z , . . . ,z )j 1 n 51, (30)

j51

0,K (z , . . . ,z )j 1 n ,1 ( j51, . . . ,n). (31) From (26,30) N(l);1, thus

z1 zn

]] ]]

K (z , . . . ,z )j 1 n 5K (j lz , . . . ,1 lz )n 5Kj

1

n , . . . , n ( j51, . . . ,n). (32)

O

zk

O

zk

2

k51 k51

Also, by (19–21), with s 5P (e :E )[R (not all values inR need to be assumed):

ij i j 11 11

H (s , . . . ,sj 11 m1, . . . ,s , . . . ,s1n mn)

5F [j F1(s , . . . ,s11 m1),F2(s , . . . ,s11 m1), . . .F1(s , . . . ,s1n mn),F2(s , . . . ,s1n mn)]

( j51, . . . ,n). (33)

We conclude by stating our regularity assumptions. About G and G we suppose only1 2

(11)

´ ´ that G (x, . . . ,x) is not constant. With (23,24) this gives (cf. (Aczel, 1987; Aczel et al.,1

1997))

m

m m

ci di

G (x , . . . ,x )1 1 m 5C

P

x ,i

O

ci±0, G ( y , . . . , y )2 1 m 5D

P

y .i i51 i51 i51

Also h , . . . ,h will be supposed locally bounded and nonconstant. We may assume,1 n

without loss of generality, that

G (1, . . . ,1)1 5G (1, . . . ,1)2 51, h (1,1)j 51 ( j51, . . . ,n). (34) So C5D51, and we have

m

m m

ci di

G (x , . . . ,x )1 1 m 5

P

x ,i

O

ci±0, G ( y , . . . , y )2 1 m 5

P

y ,i (35)

i51 i51 i51

´

In addition to these very weak conditions, we assume (cf. (Aczel et al., 1997)) that K isj injective in the following sense:

n n

9 9 9

K (z , . . . ,z )5K (z , . . . ,z ) ( j51, . . . ,n) and

O

z 5

O

z

F

j 1 n j 1 n k k

G

k51 k51 9

imply zj5zj ( j51, . . . ,n). (36)

Notice that (32) allows us to bring the sum of variables in K to 1, which we need for thej

number of equations on both sides of the implication (36) be equal (to n21, remember (30)).

Substituting (33) and (17) into (19) and (18) into (16), and equating the two expressions thus obtained for P(e :E ) ( jj 51, . . . ,n) we get, in terms of the notation (29), the system of functional equations

F [G (x , . . . ,xj 1 11 m1),G ( y , . . . , y2 11 m1), . . . ,G (x , . . . ,x1 1n mn),G ( y , . . . , y2 1n mn)]

5F (jF1[F (x , y , . . . ,x , y ), . . . ,F (x1 11 11 1n 1n 1 m1, ym1, . . . ,xmn, ymn)],

F2[F (x , y , . . . ,x , y ), . . . ,F (x1 11 11 1n 1n 1 m1, ym1, . . . ,xmn, ymn)],

:

F1[F (x , y , . . . ,x , y ), . . . ,F (xn 11 11 1n 1n n m1, ym1, . . . ,xmn, ymn)],

F2[F (x , y , . . . ,x , y ), . . . ,F (xn 11 11 1n 1n n m1, ym1, . . . ,xmn, ymn)]) ( j51, . . . ,n), (37)

(12)

a b x yj j

]]]

F (x , y , . . . ,x , y )j 1 1 n n 5 n ( j51, . . . ,n) (38)

a b

O

x yk k k51

with (35) and with aptly chosenF1andF2are the only solutions of the above equations. The answer is negative but we determine the general solutions F , . . . ,F under these1 n

assumptions and also the auxiliary functions G ,G , H , . . . ,H ,1 2 1 n F1,F2, K , . . . ,K ,1 n h , . . . ,h and M ,M (we have already N(1 n 1 2 l);1). Then we characterize the ‘two-scale Luce model with exponents’ (38) by one additional supposition.

3. Solutions

Theorem 1. If (25), (32) (36) hold, the h ’s are locally bounded but not constant inj either variable and h (1,1)51 ( j51, . . . ,n) then, for all j[h1, . . . ,nj,

j

a b

h (x, y)j 5x y (x.0, y.0) (39)

for some nonzero constants a, b.

Eq. (39) is, of course, the same as (7). Accordingly, we will write

a b

h(x, y)5h (x, y)j 5x y . (40)

Proof. Eqs. (25) and (32) imply that

h (1 mx ,1ny )1 h (n mx ,nny )n

]]]]] ]]]]]

Kj

1

n , . . . , n

O

h (k mx ,kny )k

O

h (k mx ,kny )k

2

k51 k51

h (x , y )1 1 1 h (x , y )n n n

]]]] ]]]]

5Kj

1

n , . . . , n ( j51, . . . ,n).

O

h (x , y )k k k

O

h (x , y )k k k

2

k51 k51

Thus it follows from (36) that

h (j mx ,jny )j h (x , y )j j j

]]]]]n 5]]]]n ( j51, . . . ,n),

O

h (k mx ,kny )k

O

h (x , y )k k k k51 k51

that is,

n

O

h (k mx ,kny )k h (j mx ,jny )j k51

]]]]h (x , y ) 5]]]]]n 5Q(x , . . . ,x , y , . . . , y ,1 n 1 n m,n) ( j51, . . . ,n).

j j j

O

(13)

On the right end Q carries no subscript because the middle term does not depend on j. On the other hand, the term on the left does not depend upon x , y (ll l ±j ). Writing the

same string of equations for different j’s, the middle term and thus Q remains the same but j varies on the left. So Q cannot depend on any x , y and we getj j

h (j mx ,jny )j ˜

]]]] 5Q(m,n) ( j51, . . . ,n),

h (x , y )j j j

that is,

˜

h (j mx,ny)5Q(m,n) h (x, y)j ( j51, . . . ,n).

´ The general locally bounded nonconstant solution of this equation (see e.g. Aczel, 1987)

a b ˜

is given by Q(m,n)5m n and by (39) if h (1,1)j 51. This concludes the proof of Theorem 1.

From (22) and (39) we have

a b a b

F (x , y , . . . ,x , y )j 1 1 n n 5K (x y , . . . ,x y ) ( jj 1 1 n n 51, . . . ,n). (41) Notice that, while we used (32) to get (41), conversely, the (41) form of ‘simple scalability’ ((ii) in Section 1) and the ‘conjoint Weber type II’, that is (i), imply homogeneity of degree 0 ((32), (iii)):

a b a b a b a b

K (j m n x y , . . . ,1 1 m n x y )n n 5F (j mx ,1ny , . . . ,1 mx ,nny )n a b a b

5F (x , y , . . . ,x , y )j 1 1 n n 5K (x y , . . . ,x y ) ( jj 1 1 n n 51, . . . ,n). Now, substituting (41) into (37) and applying (35) and (36), we get

m aci bdi

a b a b a b a b

P

xij yij F[K (x y , . . . ,x y ), . . . ,K (x y , . . . ,x y )]

j 11 11 1n 1n j m1 m1 mn mn i51

]]]]n m 5]]]]]]]]]]]]]]]]n

aci bdi a b a b a b a b

OP

xik yik

O

F[K (x y , . . . ,x y ), . . . ,K (xk 11 11 1n 1n k m1ym1, . . . ,xmnymn)]

i51

k51 k51

( j51, . . . ,n), (42)

where (cf. (40))

F(t , . . . ,t )1 m 5h(F1(t , . . . ,t ),1 m F2(t , . . . ,t )]1 m

a b

5F1(t , . . . ,t )1 m F2(t , . . . ,t ) .1 m (43)

b

Since on the right hand side of (42) every x figures with exponent a, multiplied by yil il a b

to give x y , also the products of powers of x and y on the left hand side can only beil il il il a b

x y or its powers. Thus we have to haveil il

m m

di5ci (i51, . . . ,m), d5

O

di5

O

ci5c±0 (44)

i51 i51

(14)

m m

ci

G (z , . . . ,z )1 1 m 5G (z , . . . ,z )2 1 m 5G(z , . . . ,z )1 m 5

P

z , ci 5

O

ci±0, (45)

i51 i51

(cf. (2)) which defines G.

a b

In view of di5c , with the notation zi ij5x yij ij (i51, . . . ,m; j51, . . . ,n), (42) becomes simpler:

m ci

P

zij F[K (z , . . . ,z ), . . . ,K (z , . . . ,z )] j 11 1n j m1 mn i51

]]]n m 5]]]]]]]]]]]]n ( j51, . . . ,n). (46)

ci

OP

zik

O

F[K (z , . . . ,z ), . . . ,K (zk 11 1n k m1, . . . ,zmn)]

i51

k51 k51

´

The following has been proved in (Aczel et al., 1997).

m

Lemma. Eqs. (30–32,36,46) and c5oi51 ci±0 are satisfied and F(t, . . . ,t) is

continuous and strictly monotonic if, and only if, the function w, given by

1 / c

w(t)5F(t, . . . ,t) (47)

is the inverse of a continuous, strictly monotonic functionc satisfying

1 ]

0# inf c(z), , sup c(z) (48)

n

0,z,` 0,z,`

and K is of the formj

K (z , . . . ,z )j 1 n 5c[z L(z , . . . ,z )] ( jj 1 n 51, . . . ,n), (49)

where w5L(z , . . . ,z ) is the unique solution of1 n n

O

c(z w)j 51,

j51

thus n

O

c(z L(z , . . . ,z ))j 1 n 51, (50)

j51

and L is homogeneous of degree (21):

21

L(lz , . . . ,1 lz )n 5l L(z , . . . ,z ).1 n (51)

We reformulate Eq. (46) of this Lemma as follows. Up to notation, (46) is the same as (42) [even (44) di5c ; (ii 51, . . . ,m) followed from (42)]. We put both sides of (42) into K , apply (44) and (32), and choosej

m

a b ci

F1(t , . . . ,t )1 m F2(t , . . . ,t )1 m 5F(t , . . . ,t )1 m 5

P

w(t ) .i (52)

i51

(15)

m m

a b ci a b ci Kj

F

P

(x y ) , . . . ,i 1 i 1

P

(x y )in in

G

i51 i51

m m

a b a b ci a b a b ci

5Kj

S

P

w[K (x y , . . . ,x y )] , . . . ,1 i 1 i 1 in in

P

w[K (x y , . . . ,x y )]n i 1 i 1 in in

D

i51 i51

( j51, . . . ,n). (53)

We trust that the reader noticed that the strange looking Eq. (53) is really (37) with (41,52,45) taken into account, the latter originating from (23) and (24) through (35) and (44).

´ It may seem that we chose (52) arbitrarily. But it has been proved in (Aczel et al., 1997) (Appendix B) that, in (46) for n.2 this is the only possibleF, while for n52

the general F is given by

m ci

F(t , . . . ,t )1 m 5T(t , . . . ,t )1 m

P

w(t )i i51

where T is an arbitrary function satisfying

T(12t , . . . ,11 2t )m 5T(t , . . . ,t )1 m (ti[]0,1[; i51, . . . ,m) (54) (for T;1 we get (52) again), cf. also Remark 8.

Thus we have proved the following.

Theorem 2. The general solution of the system (30,31,32,36,53) of functional equations 21

with continuous strictly monotonicwis given by (49), wherec 5 w has to satisfy (48) and L given by (50) has the property (51). For n52 we get the same solution if, in (53)

m c

i

each

P

i51 w[K ]j term is multiplied by a T which satisfies (54) but is otherwise arbitrary.

From the Lemma and from (41) we get

a a a b a b

F (x , y , . . . ,x , y )j 1 1 n n 5c[x y L(x y , . . . ,x y )] ( jj j 1 1 n n 51, . . . ,n), (55) which, by (16) and (17), gives explicit expressions for P(e :pE ) and P (e :E ) (ij i j 5 1, . . . ,m; j51, . . . ,n).

All these results can be summarized, as they concern the probabilities and scales, in the following main theorem

Theorem 3. Assume the following. [A]: (R, P, v, w, n) and (R, P , v , w , n) (ii i i 51, . . . ,m;

m.1) are nonatomic two-scale n-families of choice probabilities with the same

generating system (F , . . . ,F ) (i.e. (16,17) and (27,28) hold ). [B]: There exist functions1 n ˜ ˜

H , . . . ,H ,v,w,F,F, M ,M , N, injective functions K , . . . ,K , in the sense (36) and

1 n 1 2 1 2 1 n

locally bounded nonconstant functions h , . . . ,h , G ,G with1 n 1 2

(16)

such that xG (x, . . . ,x) is nonconstant and Eqs. (18–26) are satisfied. Then the1

following statements hold.

(a) There exist nonzero real numbers a,b, a continuous strictly monotonic functionc

which satisfies (48) and a function L satisfying (50) and (51) such that, for all E5he , . . . ,e1 nj[S,

a b a b a b

P(e :E )5c(v(e ) w(e ) L[v(e ) w(e ) , . . . ,v(e ) w(e ) ]), (56)

j j j 1 1 n n

a b a b a b

P (e :E )5c(v(e ) w (e ) L[v(e ) w (e ) , . . . ,v(e ) w (e ) ]) (57) i j i j i j i 1 i 1 i n i n

(i51, . . . ,m; j51, . . . ,n).

(b) Furthermore, there exist real numbers c , . . . ,c with nonzero sum such that1 n

m m

ci ci

v(e )5

P

v(e ) , w(e )5

P

w (e ) , ( j51, . . . ,n). j i j j i j

i51 i51

We have determined also the auxiliary functions:

Corollary. Assumptions [A] and [B] imply also the following:

(c) For the functions N, M ,M , G ,G , h , . . . ,h , K , . . . ,K1 2 1 2 1 n 1 n we have N(l);1 (l .0),

m c i

M (1t1, . . . ,tm)5M (2t1, . . . ,tm)5

P

i51ti (t1, . . . ,t .m 0),

m ci G (z , . . . ,z )1 1 m 5G (z , . . . ,z )2 1 m 5

P

z ,i

i51

a b

h (x, y)j 5x y (x, y.0; j51, . . . ,n),

and

K (z , . . . ,z )j 1 n 5c[z L(z , . . . ,z )] (zj 1 n j.0; j51, . . . ,n).

(d) Finally, the functions H ( jj 51, . . . ,n) are given by (33), where (55) holds for

F , . . . ,F and for1 n F1 and F2 we have m

a b ci

F1(t , . . . ,t )1 m F2(t , . . . ,t )1 m 5

P

w(t ) ,i (58)

i51

if n.2 and

m

a b ci

F1(t , . . . ,t )1 m F2(t , . . . ,t )1 m 5T(t , . . . ,t )1 m

P

w(t ) ,i (59)

i51

if n52. Here w is the inverse function of c, tj[]0,1[( j51, . . . ,m) and T is an

arbitrary function satisfying (54).

Somewhat intricate calculations show that the converse of Theorem3 and Corollary

(17)

Proposition. If (a), (b), (c), (d) hold then also [A], [B], in particular Eqs. (16–28) are satisfied.

Remark 7. One may ask the following question. If an experiment has been done, in

which various choice probabilities P (ii 51, . . . ,m) have been measured, how can it be ascertained whether there exist appropriate functions c and L, and real numbers a, b such that (57) hold. Theorem 3 shows that in principle this could be done by recognizing from the experimental data that each probability depends only upon the corresponding scale values, more exactly upon their power products, and that the P , . . . ,P1 m can be combined (aggregated) into a probability which has the same property. This aggregation should be implemented in two steps: first taking a function of P (e :E ), . . . , P (e :E )1 j m j

(the same function for j51, . . . ,n), then combining the results into what will be the aggregated probability [this is done with the functionsFand K cf. (43,33,41,40,19)]. Aj

method of finding a, b, c and L may be based again on noticing that P (e :E ) dependsi j a b

only upon v(e ) w (e ) (k51, . . . ,n), that is i k i k

a b a b

P (e :E )5K [v (e ) w (e ) , . . . ,v(e ) w (e ) ]5K (z , . . . ,z ), i j j i 1 i 1 i n i n j 1 n

which yields a, b. One could possibly also notice that, with an external functionw, the

a b

expression z 5v(e ) w(e ) may be extracted from w+K (same j ) so:

j j j j

w[K (z , . . . ,z )]j 1 n 5z L(z , . . . ,z ) ( jj 1 n 51, . . . ,n).

The requirement, that (57) should hold, gives

w[K (z , . . . ,z )]j 1 n

21 ]]]]]

c 5 w and L(z , . . . ,z )1 n 5 z .

j

If the last expression is the same for all j[h1, . . . ,njand L is homogeneous of degree 21 then we have the representations (57,56) and we know also what a, b,c and L in it are.

The above process may require, however, too much guesswork. It will therefore probably be as (or, possibly, more) feasible to test these ideas by attempting to fit data with the representation (57). We only touch on the relevant model fitting issues here; as indicated earlier, related issues are discussed in detail in Townsend and Landon (1982), Ashby et al. (1994), Estes (1997), Bamber and van Santen (2000), and in Myung et al. (2000). In the present paper (also in this Remark) we have assumed and continue to assume that the scales v, w (i51, . . . ,m) are known; the model fitting issues are

i i

similar, though more complex, when the scales have also to be estimated from data. We also continue to assume that only the P (ii 51, . . . ,m) are observable, i.e., we want to fit the data with a representation that satisfies (57) and thus can be aggregated into a P as represented in (56). Again, the model fitting issues are similar, though more complex, when P is also observable.

(18)

21 a b

c [P (e :E )] v(e ) w (e ) i j i j i j

]]]]21 5]]]]a b.

c [P (e :E )] v(e ) w (e ) i k i k i k

Thus one should search for the ‘best fitting’ function c and parameters a, b, using traditional and newly developing techniques. (For instance, one might compare the fit of c(t)5t (corresponding to a two-scale Luce model with exponents) to that ofc(t)5t1

1 / 2 ˜ ˜

t ). Once one has the ‘best fitting’ function c, the estimate L of L can be taken to be the solution of

n ˜ ˜

O

c[z L(z , . . . ,z )]j 1 n 51.

j51

Our task is easier when we have data for (at least) two sets E, E9 with two (or more) common elements, say e , e . Then, for (57) to hold, we must havej k

21 21

c [P (e :E )]i j c [P (e :Ei j 9)]

]]]]21 5]]]]21 .

c [P (e :E )]i k c [P (e :Ei k 9]

Whenc(t)5t, we have an observable property of the representation. In general, we can

first determine the functionc that gives the ‘best fit’ to equality for these (and similar) ratios, then turn to the estimation of the exponents a, b and of the function L.

Remark 8. On the other hand, as mentioned, while (58), (57) and (43) determine F, even ignoring T there is some arbitrariness left form m F1 andF2: even if F1(t , . . . ,t )1 m 5

Ai Bi

P

i51 t ,i F2(t , . . . ,t )1 m 5

P

i51 t , we have only aAi i1bBi5c (ii 51, . . . ,m) as restriction. Notice, however, that already in the calculations in Section 1 we used the

a b

function F 5 F F1 2 for aggregation, rather than the individual functions F1,F2. Actually, we could write (37) as (cf. (53))

K (h [G (x , . . . ,xj 1 1 11 m1),G ( y , . . . , y2 11 m1], . . . ,h [G (x , . . . ,xn 1 1n mn),G ( y , . . . , y2 1n mn])

5K [j F(K [h (x , y ), . . . ,h (x , y )], . . . ,K [h (x1 1 11 11 n 1n 1n 1 1 m1, ym1), . . . ,h (xn mn, ymn)]),

:

F(K [h (x , y ), . . . ,h (x , y )], . . . ,K [h (xn 1 11 11 n 1n 1n n 1 m1, ym1), . . . ,h (xn mn, ymn)])]

( j51, . . . ,n), (60)

which has the advantage of containing F rather thanF1 andF2, although it does not look simpler than (37). But the symmetry in having bothF1 andF2 as counterparts of

G and G may be attractive, even though it turns out eventually that G1 2 15G (but in2

general F1±F2). Ultimately the choice between (37) and (60) is a matter of taste.

Remark 9. The above Proposition shows that without adding further assumptions to [A]

(19)

(48), (50), (51), respectively. One further restriction will complete the characterization of two-scale Luce models with exponents in the next section.

4. Characterization of the ‘two-scale Luce model with exponents’

In order to get (38), that is (9), characterized, we aim to obtainw(t)5t because then

c(s)5s, so that (55) reduces to

a b a b a b

F (x , y , . . . ,x , y )j 1 1 n n 5x y L(x y , . . . ,x y ) ( jj j 1 1 n n 51, . . . ,n). (61) Summing from 1 to n we get, in view of (27),

n

a b a b a b

15

O

x y L(x y , . . . ,x y ),k k 1 1 n n k51

that is,

1

a b a b

]]]

L(x y , . . . ,x y )1 1 n n 5 n ,

a b

O

x yk k k51

so that (61) indeed becomes (38):

a b x yj j

]]]

F (x , y , . . . ,x , y )j 1 1 n n 5 n , ( j51, . . . ,n).

a b

O

x yk k k51

If w(t)5t then F(t , . . . ,t ) given by (52) will be, cf. (45),1 m m

ci

F(t , . . . ,t )1 m 5

P

ti 5G(t , . . . ,t ).1 m (62)

i51

Conversely, if (62) holds then, by (47) and (44),

1

]c Sc /Sci i

w(t)5F(t, . . . ,t) 5t 5t.

[As we saw before Theorem 2, (52) and thus (62) is a possible choice for n52 and the only choice for n.2]. So we have the following.

Theorem 4. The choice probabilities in the ‘two-scale Luce model with exponents’, that is those given by (1) or equivalently by (9), and only these satisfy, in addition to the conditions in Theorem 2 or Theorem 3, also F 5G.

Remark 10. Till now we supposed that G (x, . . . ,x) is not constant, that is, see (45),1

m m

oi51 ci±0. Conversely, oi51 ci50 means that G (x, . . . ,x) is constant. But1

(20)

a b C x yj j j

]]]

F (x , y , . . . ,x , y )j 1 1 n n 5 n ( j51, . . . ,n), (63)

a b

O

C x yk k k k51

where C , . . . ,C are positive constants (the proof uses a method similar to that in1 n

´

Section 4 of (Aczel et al., 1997)).

The representation in (63) has interesting psychological interpretations. The form indicates that the ordinal position of an option e in the set E affects its representation — in particular, option e in position j has a ‘weighting’ parameter C placed in front of itsj j

a b

(e.g. overall) scale valuev(e ) w(e ) . Returning to the noise burst example in Section 1, j j

one could think of the stimuli e ( jj 51, . . . ,n), as being presented in temporal order, with e being presented before ej j11 for j51, . . . ,n21. The weight C then might bej

interpreted as a bias to report the stimulus in position j as louder or softer than its scale values would indicate; alternatively, C might be interpreted as a memory effect, withj

stimuli at different positions in the sequence not being equally represented relative to their scale values.

5. Conclusion: open problem

´

In this paper we have extended results in (Aczel et al., 1997) to the aggregation of two-scale homogeneous, simply scalable, conjoint Weber type II families of choice probabilities. The further extension to more than two components is routine. The proofs required us to assume that the representations are simply scalable (Eq. (22)) in order that we can use an appropriate injectivity condition (Eq. (36)). The essence of the injectivity condition used in this paper (and in (1)) is that (certain combinations of) the parameters of the model are identifiable from the data. It would be of interest to develop results that do not require the use of simple scalability as a means to get to an appropriate injectivity condition.

Consider, for instance, the following generalization of the ‘similarity choice model’ (5):

P(r[e ]j ue :E )k 5F [jh(e ,r[e ]),k 1 b(r[e ]), . . . ,1 h(e ,r[e ]),k n b(r[e ])] ( j,kn 51, . . . ,n) (64)

(E5he , . . . ,e1 nj), where the scalesh and b satisfy (cf. (6)) 0#h(e ,e )j k #1, h(e ,e )j k 5h(e ,e ),k j h(e ,e )j j 51,

n

0#b(r[e ])j #1,

O

b(r[e ])k 51 ( j,k51, . . . ,n). (65)

k51

Assume that the model is ‘identifiable’ (cf. Bamber and van Santen (2000)) in the sense that, if

(21)

5F [jh9(e ,r[e ]),k 1 b9(r[e ]), . . . ,1 h9(e ,r[e ]),k n b9(r[e ])]n

for all j, k51, . . . ,n and for the scalesh,b andh9,b9 satisfying (65), then

h(e ,e )j k 5h9(e ,e ) andj k b(r[e ])j 5b9(r[e ]) ( j,kj 51, . . . ,n).

Notice that this property resembles, but also differs from, the injectivity (36). The ‘similarity choice model’ (5) is a model ‘identifiable’ in the sense just stated (cf. e.g. (Townsend and Landon, 1982)). It is an open problem what the general ‘identifiable’ solutions of a system of equations for F ( jj 51, . . . ,n) in (64), corresponding to (37) (or to (60)), are — and what should be supposed, for adjusting the number of equations to the number of parameters (scale values), in place of an analogue of the simple scalability (22) and such properties of the functions h ( jj 51, . . . ,n) therein as (25) and (26). Closely related questions are considered in Bamber and van Santen (2000).

Acknowledgements

This research has been supported by the Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council of Canada (NSERC) collaborative project grant no. CPG 0164211 and in part by the Hungarian National Foundation for Scientific Research (OTKA), grant No. T-030082 and by the Hungarian High Educational Research and Development Found (FKFP), grant No. 0310 / 1997. The authors are grateful to the referee and to the consulting editor for helpful suggestions.

References

´

Aczel, J., 1987. A Short Course on Functional Equations Based Upon Recent Applications in the Social and Behavioral Sciences, Reidel–Kluwer, Dordrecht / Boston, pp. 52–56.

´

Aczel, J., Maksa, Gy., Marley, A.A.J., Moszner, Z., 1997. Consistent aggregation of scale families of selection probabilities. Mathematical Social Sciences 33, 227–250.

Ashby, F.G., Maddox, W.T., Lee, W.W., 1994. On the dangers of averaging across subjects when using multidimensional scaling or the similarity choice model. Psychological Science 5, 144–151.

Bamber, D., van Santen, J.P.H., 2000. How to tell whether a model is testable: The example of the discrete-state selective-influence model, to appear in Journal of Mathematical Psychology 44.

Estes, W.K., 1997. Some reflections on the role of the choice model in theories of categorization, identification, and learning. In: Marley, A.A.J. (Ed.), Choice, Decision, and Measurement: Essays in Honor of R. Duncan Luce, Erlbaum, Mahwah, NJ, pp. 321–328.

Falmagne, J.-C., 1981. On a recurrent misuse of a classical unctional equation result. Journal of Mathematical Psychology 3, 190–193.

Falmagne, J.-C., Iverson, G., 1979. Conjoint Weber laws and additivity. Journal of Mathematical Psychology 20, 164–183.

Luce, R.D., 1963. Detection and recognition. In: Luce, R.D., Bush, R.R., Galanter, E. (Eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Psychology, Vol. 1, Wiley, New York, pp. 103–189, in particular 113–116.

Marley, A.A.J., 1982. Random utility models with all choice probabilities expressible as ‘functions’ of the binary choice probabilities. Mathematical Social Sciences 3, 39–56.

(22)

identification and preference. In: Ashby, F.G. (Ed.), Multidimensional Models of Perception and Cognition, Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp. 299–333.

Myung, I.J., Browne, M., Foster, M. (Eds.), 2000. Special issue on model selection, Journal of Mathematical Psychology 44.

´

Renyi, A., 1970. In: Probability Theory, North-Holland–Elsevier, Amsterdam / New York, pp. 81–84. Townsend, J.T., Landon, D.E., 1982. An experimental and theoretical investigation of the constant-ratio rule

Referensi

Dokumen terkait

Diajukan Untuk Memenuhi Salah Satu Syarat Sidang Guna Memperoleh Gelar Ahli Madya. Program Studi

Berdasarkan Penetapan Pemenang oleh Kelompok Kerja V (Lima) Unit Layanan Pengadaan (ULP) Kabupaten Hulu Sungai Selatan, tang8al 24 Agustus 2011, dengan ini diumumkan

Model optimasi E conom ic Order Quantity dengan sistem parsial backorder dan increm ental discount dapat digunakan dalam masalah manajemen persediaan yang

United Tractors pusat yang terdiri dari modul knowledge service dan spareparts, pengetahuan pada modul-modul knowledge service dan spareparts ini sangat berguna dalam membantu

Maka Bersama ini diumumkan bahwa Lelang dinyatakan Gagal karena dari 3 (tiga)penyedia yang memasukan Dokumen Penawaran, tidak ada yang Lulus Evaluasi Administrasi.

The Thai Government is formed according to the democratic prin- ciples of parliamentary system and constitutional monarchy. Apart from the fundamental state policies to

[r]

R}NCANA UMUM PENGADAAN MDLALUI SWAKELOLA NAMA IOI-ID/I.. TAEUN