• Tidak ada hasil yang ditemukan

The environment of social evolution

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2018

Membagikan "The environment of social evolution"

Copied!
11
0
0

Teks penuh

(1)

Introduction

he relationship between human communities and their environments has been an enduring theme in archaeology since the discipline turned away from the writing of cultural histories and towards economic and social archaeology (e.g. Clark 1939; 1952). In this context the environment was taken to be the ‘natural’, if humanly modiied, world that was occupied by human populations.In some studies the human – environment relationship has been treated as if it were a matter of a determinacy with the organization of human behaviour being predicated upon the environments that were available to a population that had at its command a particular level of technology (Binford 2001). In other cases the emphasis has been upon social and political obligations driving the human exploitation and circulation of material resources (Friedman and Rowlands 1977), and yet others have sought to place even greater emphasis upon the ways cultural schemes of understanding directed people’s use of the landscape (Tilley 1994).

In all these cases human behaviour, however it may be motivated, appears to design the relationships between the members of a community, and between that community and its environment. However, the relationship between individuals and their environments is also central to Darwinian evolution. his claims to account for the survival of particular forms of life as resulting from the environmental selection of individual reproductive itness from a wider spectrum of potentially randomly generated possibilities. But the Darwinian paradigm does not treat the animal and plant populations as instigating the design of their own environmental adaptations, other than by the default mechanism of carrying from one generation to the next a range of possibilities, some of which are preserved by environmental selection whilst others become extinct. Within this process environmental modiication by the organism, such as the beaver’s lodge, might be treated as an extension of the behaviour that has been selected for (Dawkins 1999). By way of contrast, archaeologists treat human behaviour as socially responsive and intentionally directed towards adapting to an environmental stimulus or towards ordering the environment according to social demands or conceptual schemes. hus, if we were to characterize the irst of these human

oF soCIal evoluTIon

(2)

strategies, that which responds to environmental stimuli, as environmental determinism it would not mean that we could also characterize it as being Darwinian. In addition, cultural studies that claim to be Darwinian because they concern themselves with the ways human cultural behaviour designs an adaptation towards particular environmental constraints (o’Brien 1996) miss the point. Human intentionality and natural selection are not one and the same because each assumes a diferent approach to the design of life’s trajectory (cf. Fodor and Piatelli-Palmarini 2010).

his brings us to the central problem of human behaviour: if the history of human behavioural variation is not structured by Darwinian principles for the selection of individual reproductive itness then must we assume that humanity has evolved a non-Darwinian intentionality and, if so, how has this come about? one common solution is to suggest that whilst modern humans are certainly the biological products of Darwinian evolution, the evolutionary process has none the less resulted in the selection of a kind of cognitive and behavioural ‘plasticity’ that subsequently enabled humanity to design self-motivated responses to environmental conditions (Tooby and Cosmides 1992). Consequently human history would seem to represent a new kind of dual evolutionary process, in part the product of the natural selection of inherited characteristics (cognitive plasticity), and in part driven by the success or failure of cognitive schemes designed to cope with, and to modify, given material conditions.

Evolution and the problem of social behaviour

evolution is deployed in archaeological narratives in two ways. It is used to evoke the forward movement of history, implying a sense of direction traced in stages of social or economic organization, and it describes the lineages of artefact and assemblage types through time (and their dispersal across space) (shennan 2009). hus evolutionary sequences trace a path along which one condition gives rise to another through selected modiications. However archaeology claims not only to describe but to also explain the sequences that it reveals and these explanations tend to be causal. evolution thus becomes a trope in the archaeological literature when it claims to show how each stage of history is caused by certain pre-existing forces or conditions.

as we have already noted, Darwinian evolution explains the diversity of life as the product of two processes: individually inherited variability acted upon by natural selection (Godfrey-smith 2009). ernst mayr made the point that before Darwin, species were deined normatively in the terms of ideal types. Darwin changed that characterization of life’s forms by introducing ‘population thinking’. Darwinian evolution is only possible because a species comprises populations of diverse individuals upon which natural selection can act (mayr 1976, 26–9). he key to the biological evolutionary process therefore appears to lie with the variable success of each line of inherited traits distributed among the members of a population: it is these lines that are variously maintained or extinguished over time by natural selection.

(3)

variability. It was the rediscovery of mendelian genetics at the beginning of the twentieth century, and the establishment of the structure of Dna in the 1950s, that secured the claim that an individual’s biological form and various (but not necessarily all) of its behavioural characteristics were genetically inherited. By the 1960s it had become commonly assumed that natural selection decides which genetic lineages will be successful in surviving across the generations by virtue of the relative ‘itness’ of the physical characteristics that they facilitate. hus we arrive at the still dominant view that explains phenotypical variations in individuals as the product of a genetic determinate, and the history of populations as determined by natural selection.

at its simplest, this model of natural history emphasizes competition between individuals within a population for success in reproduction and therefore genetic transmission (Dawkins 1978). his model, needless to say, presents us with something of a puzzle. many animals have evolved to live in populations whose behavioural integration is described by the ways individual organisms respond to each other or submit to ‘social’ patterns of behaviour. However, if a population is made up of individuals competing for higher levels of itness to facilitate the widest possible transmission of their genetic inheritance, then why should some populations evolve characteristics of social integration in which the itness to reproduce for some individuals is put at risk, reduced, or indeed sacriiced entirely to the beneit of other members of the social group? In the animal kingdom this is most clearly exempliied by the evolution of eusocial behaviour, where a biological population is divided between labour roles, each with variable reproductive potential, to care for a brood within a defended kin-based colony (Wilson 2012).

he evolution of altruistic behaviour that describes a biological individual’s commitment to a social existence therefore appears to run counter to the Dawkins’ principle of genetic ‘selishness’: it exposes altruists to likely exploitation by selish individuals who occupy the same social group (sterelny and Griiths 1999, 153f.). he initial temptation to explain altruism as facilitating increased group itness was rejected by Williams (1966) who argued that, under natural selection, no mechanism existed at group level to ix the inheritance of altruistic behaviour at the level of the individual. Genes are certainly passed on from one generation to the next but they are transmitted through individual ‘vehicles’: there is no group medium of transmission to design a group level of itness. his appeared to counter the notion that natural selection could operate at a number of levels of biological organization, from individuals to groups (okasha 2006).

(4)

and that this would explain both the competition for individual itness and the individual sacriices made in the evolution of altruism among genetically related individuals.

Inclusive itness represented the apogee of the gene centred view of evolution. Dawkins followed Hamilton to promulgate the view that whilst genes ‘cause’ or sustain certain traits upon which natural selection operates, it is only genes that are replicated. herefore, whilst individual vehicles live and die, it is those genes that are selected for that achieve a degree of immortality (Dawkins 1999).

he problem of human social evolution

If inclusive itness does account for eusociality, the explanation seems diicult to extend to include the complex social organizations that mark the evolution of humanity. Kinship terminologies are certainly widely used to deine relationships of human solidarity within small-scale societies wherein acts of altruism routinely occur, but kinship terminology is not the same thing as genetic kinship, and human societies expand to include many non-kin obligatory relationships.

In his Sociobiology: he New Synthesis (Wilson 1975) e. o. Wilson employed inclusive itness as the guiding principle of social activity across the animal kingdom. He garnered considerable controversy in so doing through his inclusion of humanity among the species whose social behaviour rested upon that same biological determinate. Having adopted this position he had little choice other than claim that many controversial aspects of human behaviour, including aggression and engendered divisions of labour, were determined by our biology (Barlow and silverberg 1980; Kitcher 1985; cf. Wilson 1978; 1999).

more recently, and more controversially still, Wilson has abandoned the model of inclusive itness (nowack et al. 2010). His current position attempts to preserve, without recourse to Hamilton’s rule, the principle that altruistic behaviour ensures genetic beneit, often at some individual reproductive cost to a subset of the social population. he argument prompts Wilson to return to ideas of group selection where the evolution of social groups emerged on those occasions when the non-dispersal of ofspring who have reached maturity occurred. according to Wilson this gave rise to the development of colony-based life that reduced risks to most of its members and protected the brood of the next generation. his development requires altruistic behaviour to out-compete the behaviour of selish free-loaders within the group. From mechanisms that are not entirely clear in Wilson’s account, the pressures of inter-group competition for resources are held to be those that dominate the processes of selection acting on individuals within the group, thus sustaining within group co-operative behaviour and the ixing of the institutional behaviours displayed in social populations (Wilson 2012).

Social evolution and evolutionary development

(5)

genes as replicators and organisms as vehicles by Dawkins expressed a particular reading of Darwin’s thesis. For Dawkins evolution was a narrative concerning the transmission of a genetic optimon, which he deined as the unit of selection that passes between parent and ofspring (Dawkins 1999, 81). he story of evolution by this reading was simply the story of that which is transmitted and for which, as Dawkins’s use of the term implied, the organism merely acts as a vehicle.

However, for the organism to be able to transmit anything by means of reproduction it has irst to grow to maturity. Without development there can be no reproduction and the primacy of development before reproduction occurs within, and is dependent upon, the wider conditions of gestation, nurture, and the availability of sources of energy to feed the organism’s own metabolism (oyama 2000; oyama et al. 2001). Development is not therefore generated out of some act of genomic creationism, but is built using the information provided by, among many other things, the genome and the environment within which that genome is situated. his more complex environmental context extends from the chemical structure of the fertilized cell, the body of the parent who, in the case of sexual reproduction, gestates and sustains the fertilized egg, to the metabolism and cellular reproduction of the organism’s own body, and the wider environment from which energy (food, light, warmth) and security are obtained in every stage of this process. In this self-creation the organism emerges as it creates a boundary between itself and its environment, thus forming its identity as a biological individual (Casper 1994). such boundaries are always semi-permeable for they have to allow the importation of energy to sustain the organism’s metabolism. he organism is also conscious in as much as it adjusts its development relative to its environment. he dogmatic demand that the organism’s deinition be reduced to a genetic blueprint that determines the assemblage of inherited traits that exist within and are, in turn, selected for survival by, an external environmental arbiter is therefore an inaccurate characterisation of a far more complex process. Indeed, the inter-dependency established between the organism and its environment should perhaps be more accurately described as a relationship of symbiosis in which each are entangled in a process of co-evolution (margulis 1991; odling-smee et al. 2003).

(6)

he archaeology of social complexity

In his review of the relationship between human biological and social evolution Benoît Dubreuil links the origins of human social complexity to the growth in community size and the origins of social hierarchies (Dubreuil 2010). He achieves this by proposing that the evolution of various forms of corporate identity has been accompanied by the emergent authority of ‘salient individuals’ who personiied key values used in deining these corporate groups. Dubreuil ofers a functionalist account as to why corporate groups come into being in the irst place, and why their development was supposedly accompanied by the development of hierarchies. He argues that the egalitarian systems that are widely used to characterise hunter-gatherer stages of development required group members to share in the responsibilities for monitoring various strictures against self-aggrandisers who might otherwise fragment the group. For such notionally egalitarian communities, socially responsive behaviours would have to out-compete selishness. he information any one individual would require in monitoring all other individuals in such situations would however have been considerable, and this, Dubreuil believes, would have limited group size: individuals would simply not have been able to cope with the interpersonal demands of networking across an increasingly enlarging community. For Dubreuil the structuring of populations into corporate groups therefore meant that because individuals were now assigned to general categories of identity then the amount of information that any group member needed to monitor the trustworthiness of others was reduced. Consequently, individuals could operate in much larger communities that now comprised a limited number for corporate groups. Dubreuil also proposes that ‘salient individuals’ might then have emerged to represent group values, allowing for a situation in which “certain members of a corporate group are often made implicitly or explicitly responsible for enforcing norms within the group” (Dubreuil 2010: 166). hese individuals were in some way empowered to decide when and how sanctions might be applied against transgressors. he model Dunbreuil develops thus allows for hierarchies of authority pertaining to those who speak for the values and intentions assigned to corporate groups. It also allows us to diferentiate between the accumulation of moral claims to such authority, and the accumulation of wealth as access to material resources: these represent two diferent trajectories towards social diferentiation (Dubreuil 2010, 175f.).

Dubreuil is not alone in characterizing the human world of social institutions as a simpliication of the complexities assumed to be confronted by members of primate and early hominin communities (strum and latour 1987; Bloch 2008). Bloch, for example, refers to human social structures as being transcendental in that they exist independently of the particular individuals who might inhabit them. searle refers to these transcendental qualities as ‘social facts’ that are objectiied by humanity’s use of language (searle 2010). If we were to follow searle then language would appear to give the institutions that make up a social structure a reality in terms of contractual values that are discursively expressed as the rules that members are obligated to uphold. language also puts in place the secondary rules that establish how transgressions are to be managed.

(7)

evolutionary question: what drove the change from the complex transactional negotiation of alliances between individuals to the simpler process of identifying types of individuals by reference to transcendental groups? he functionalist answer followed by Dubreuil, amongst others, is that the change solved the ‘problem’ posed by the psychological restriction to community size wherein human relations were individually negotiated. such teleological reasoning fails however because the ‘problem’ that behavioural change supposedly solved need never have existed in the irst place. here is no reason for thinking that groups of hunter-gatherers could not simply have continued to operate as relatively dispersed populations as they had done for several millennia (and during which time they managed to colonize most of the globe). his had clearly proven to be an entirely competent adaptive arrangement, and not one that would have prompted the ‘need’ for the complex and protracted process of non-kin based social evolution.

Darwinian evolution denies that any biological trait, sustained across generations, is designed by the organism to fulil a pre-deined task (despite the loose claims, employed in many evolutionary accounts, that such and such a trait exits to do something or other). such traits are supposedly generated without prior direction, and those that do survive from one generation to the next are ixed by natural selection. Indeed, to suggest that a particular trait came into being to solve an adaptive problem for future generations results in narratives that look worryingly like those of creationism or intelligent design. In Darwinian evolution a newly generated trait survives either because it has a neutral value for the organism’s itness or because it its into a pre-existing design space formed by the environment. However, if we consider the organism as a developing being which, as we have already noted, seeks a place for itself in a sustaining environment then, from the perspective of autopoiesis, such beings are conscious and directed towards the world because their development is built from a self-awareness towards the conditions necessary for their survival and growth. a simple example of this would be the organism’s move towards food and away from poison (hompson 2007). In this context of ‘self-making’, traits are developed and sustained by the necessity of bringing the organism to maturity. he corporate groups that manifest themselves as social institutions were not therefore invented to solve the non-existent problem of community size, but once those corporate groups had begun to evolve then growth of community size may have become possible for the reasons that have already been outlined, and complex social structures could have begun to emerge.

(8)

from a reduction in the work expenditure required of an individual in the procurement of food from source. Both of these developments, in food procurement and cooking, would surely have required some growth in the scale of social co-operation. Indeed, increased brain size among hominins “emerges as strongly related to increases in social group size ... [and] a deeper relationship with behavioural indices of social complexity” (Dunbar and shultz 2007, 656): the implication is that it was the growth in networks of social complexity that carried brain and cognitive development forward (cf. Dunbar and shultz 2007; Gamble 2010) rather than the other way around. hus we still need to identify the proto-social behaviours that sustained the evolution of social and cognitive development.

once we recognize that individual development is central to evolution then we must accept that individuals grow to maturity by processing semantic information about their environments. he path of developmental evolution that concerns us here is that which was traced by hominins when they extended the information that recognised an individual’s presence by its bodily expression of age, sexuality, aggressiveness or submissiveness to include the recognition that an individual body also expresses certain transcendental categories and that these categories could be objectiied. an early, and obvious, example of this is the objectiication of femaleness that becomes represented by a particular body form in the igurines of the upper Palaeolithic of eurasia. such general qualities, expressed in the bodies of individuals, could also be extended to include diferent kinds of skills expressed in particular performances and to the kinds of places that individual performances might occupy. he development of material culture can now be seen as the driving force in the elaboration of this process (Barrett 2013). Individuals will have become recognizable as expressing certain categories of personhood in the ways they responded to the commonly accepted qualities inherent in things, and those qualities could be extended and elaborated upon in the production and use of kinds of material culture and areas of architectural space. In other words, categories of being were objectiied in performance before they could be represented discursively.

(9)

notes, is that wisdom is “accredited to those who claim that materiality represents the merely apparent, behind which lies that which is real” (miller 2005, 1; cf. Bloch 2008). security in things includes seeing others as having a commonality with the self, and the variable qualities of others might be recognised in the ways that they exemplify their recognition of, or indeed access to, the grounding of a commonly accepted cosmology. Whist threats to the self are undoubtedly posed by the unknown they may also appear to be harboured by those whose actions seem to deny the accepted order of things.

let me emphasise that these schemes of order and value were not intellectual abstractions imposed by a ‘social intelligence’ upon the world, but instead they were discovered empirically, as material realities that sustained the self ’s development, a form of “sense making” in the practical living and growing amongst things (hompson 2007; Barrett 2013). hese schemes found discursive expression in a “science of the concrete” (lévi-strauss 1966, 1f) and their discovery as a way of being in the world conirms latour’s demand that the social has never been a condition that can be recognized when puriied by the exclusion of its material and natural components but is fundamentally a hybrid of all these things (latour 1993). such hybridization has immediate implications for archaeology. If the growth and development of an individual human is never internally (i.e. genetically) generated but is instead a process of self-construction that ‘entangles’ the developing being within communities whose material practices conirm certain cosmological or moral orders to the world (Hodder 2012), then many cultural assemblages may have emerged out of building the environmental contexts that enabled normative judgements of behaviour to be made and upon which co-operation and trust depended (cf. Tomasello 2009).

he beaker assemblage of late neolithic europe is surely one very obvious archaeological example of such an emergent material order. It seems to be increasingly unnecessary to struggle with proposed typological sequences that seek to describe the ‘spread’ of the beaker phenomenon, let alone search for a point for its origin (cf. Fokkens 2012, 116). he complex local traditions that converged towards a hybrid assemblage comprising of personal appearance, traditions of artefact production (Boast 1995) along, presumably, with the etiquette of serving drink (cf. sherratt 1987), and the attempts to ind, across many regions, a common grammar in death rituals (Fitzpatrick 2011, 208f.), all will certainly have displayed lengthy and complex histories. But these are histories of the pragmatics by which niche environments could be constructed in the process of sustaining the evolution of a commonly understood kind of human behaviour. Indeed if, as seems likely, the third millennium BCe witnessed signiicant levels of human mobility across europe (larsson and Parker Pearson 2007, 41f.), then the success of those movements will have depended upon participants being able to colonize a recognizable cultural environment: in other words to feel ‘at home’.

Conclusion

(10)

former results in barren description (of which we have more than enough), whilst our theorizing requires that we make reference to the material itself (neustupný 1971). since the 1960s the relationship between these two aspects of archaeological practice has been the source of considerable debate. his contribution is ofered in the belief that archaeology is the exploration of the profoundly diicult question of how we should view humanity and its place within the wider trajectories of historical materialism.

References

Barlow, G. W. and silverberg, J. (eds) 1980. Sociobiology: Beyond Nature/Nurture? Reports Deinitions and Debate

(american association for the advancement of science: selected symposium 35). Boulder: Westview Press.

Barrett, J. C. 2013. he archaeology of mind: It’s not what you think. Cambridge Archaeological Journal

23(1), 1–17.

Binford, l. R. 2001. Constructing Frames of Reference: An Analytical Method for Archaeological heory Building Using Ethnographic and Environmental Data. Berkeley: university of California Press.

Bloch, m. 2008. Why religion is nothing special but is central. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society

(B) 363, 2055–61.

Boast, R. 1995. Fine pots, pure pots, Beaker pots. In I. Kinnes and G. varndell (eds), ‘Unbaked Urns of Rudely Shape’: Essays on British and Irish Pottery for Ian Longworth, 55–67. oxford: oxbow Books.

Casper, m. J. 1994. Reframing and grounding nonhuman agency: What makes a foetus an agent? American Behavioral Scientist 37(6), 839–56.

Clark, J. G. D. 1939. Archaeology and Society. london: methuen.

Clark, J. G. D. 1952. Prehistoric Europe: he Economic Basis. london: methuen.

Darwin C. 1872. he Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (6th edn).

Dawkins, R. 1978. he Selish Gene. london: Granada Publishing.

Dawkins, R. 1999. he Extended Phenotype: he Long Reach of the Gene (revised edition). oxford: oxford university Press.

Douglas, m. 1966. Purity and Danger: An Analysis of the Concepts of Pollution and Taboo. london: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Douglas, m. 1978. Natural Symbols: Explorations in Cosmology. Harmondsworth: Penguin education. Dubreuil, B. 2010. Human Evolution and the Origins of Hierarchies: he State of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge

university Press.

Dunbar, R. I. m. 1998. he social brain hypothesis. Evolutionary Anthropology 6, 178–90.

Dunbar, R. I. m. and shulz, s. 2007. understanding primate brain evolution. Proceedings of the Transactions of the Royal Society (B) 362, 649–58.

Fitzpatrick, a. P. 2011. he Amesbury Archer and the Boscombe Bowmen: Bell Beaker Burials at Boscombe Down, Amesbury, Wiltshire. salisbury: Wessex archaeology.

Fodor, J. and Piatelli-Palmarini, m. 2010. What Darwin Got Wrong. london: Proile Books.

Fokkens, H. 2012. Dutchmen on the move? a discussion of the adoption of Beaker pottery. In m. J. allen, J. Gardiner and a. sheridan (eds) Is here a British Chalcolithic? People, Places and Polity in the late 3rd Millennium, 115–25. oxford: Prehistoric society Research Paper 4

Friedman, J. and Rowlands, m. 1977. notes towards an epigenetic model of the evolution of ‘civilisation’. In J. Friedman and m. Rowlands (eds), he Evolution of Social Systems, 201–76. london: Duckworth. Gamble, C. 2010. Technologies of separation and the evolution of social extension. In R. Dunbar, C. Gamble

and J. Gowlett (eds), Social Brain, Distributed Mind, 17–42. oxford: oxford university Press for he British academy.

(11)

Hamilton, W. D. 1964. he genetic evolution of social behaviour (parts I and II). Journal of heoretical Biology

7, 1–16.

Hodder, I. 2012. Entangled: An Archaeology of the Relationships between Humans and hings, Chichester; Wiley-Blackwell.

Kitcher, P. 1985. Vaulting Ambition: Sociobiology and the Quest for Human Nature. Cambridge ma: mIT Press. larsson, m. and Parker Pearson, m. (eds) 2007. From Stonehenge to the Baltic: Living with Cultural Diversity

in the hird Millennium BC. oxford: archaeopress.

latour, B. 1993. We Have Never Been Modern. london: longman.

leach, e. 1976. Culture and Communication: he Logic by Which Symbols are Connected. Cambridge: Cambridge university Press.

lévi-strauss, C. 1966. he Savage Mind. london: Weidenfeld and nicolson.

margulis, l. 1991. symbiogenesis and symbionticism. In l. margulis and R. Fester (eds), Symbiosis as a Source of Evolutionary Innovation: Speciation and Morphogenesis, 1–14. Cambridge ma: mIT Press.

maturana, H. R. and varela, F. J. 1998. he Tree of Knowledge: he Biological Roots of Human Understanding. Boston ma: shambhala Publications.

mayr, e. 1976. Evolution and the Diversity of Life: Selected Essays. Cambridge ma: Harvard university Press. miller, D. 2005. materiality: an introduction. In D. miller (ed.), Materiality. london: Duke university Press. neustupný, e. 1971. Whither archaeology? Antiquity 45, 34–9.

nowak, m. a., Tarnita, C. e. and Wilson, e. o. 2010. he evolution of eusociality, Nature 466, 1057–62. o’Brian, m. J. 1996. Evolutionary Archaeology: heory and Application. salt lake City: university of utah Press. odling-smee, F. J., laland, K.n. and Feldman, m. W. 2003. Niche Construction: he Neglected Process in

Evolution. Princeton: Princeton university Press.

okasha, s. 2006. Evolution and the Levels of Selection. oxford: oxford university Press

oyama, s. 2000. he Ontogeny of Information: Developmental Systems and Evolution (2nd edition revised), Durham nC: Duke university Press.

oyama, s., Griiths P. e. and Gray, R. D. (eds) 2001. Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution.

Cambridge ma: he mIT Press.

searle, J. R. 2010. Making the Social World: he Structure of Human Civilization. oxford: oxford university Press.

shennan, s. (ed.) 2009. Pattern and Process in Cultural Evolution. Berkeley: university of California Press. sherratt, a. 1987. Cups that cheered. In W. Waldren and R. Kennard (eds), Bell Beakers of the Western

Mediterranean: the Oxford International Conference 1986, 81–106 (British archaeological Report 76). oxford: British archaeological Reports.

sterenly, K. and Griiths, P. e. 1999. Sex and Death: An Introduction to Philosophy of Biology. Chicago: university of Chicago Press.

strum, s. s. and latour, B. 1987. Redeining the social link: from baboons to humans. Social Science Information

26, 783–802.

hompson, e. 2007. Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Cambridge mass: Belknap Press.

Tilley, C. 1994. A Phenomenology of Landscape: Places, Paths and Monuments. london: Berg. Tilley, C. 1999. Metaphor and Material Culture. oxford: Blackwell.

Tomasello, m. 2009. Why We Cooperate. Cambridge ma: mIT Press

Tooby, J. and Cosmides, l. 1992. he psychological foundations of culture. In J. H. Barkow, l. Cosmides and J. Tooby (eds), he Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, 19–136. oxford: oxford university Press.

Wiliams, G. C. 1996. adaptation and natural eelection: a Critique of some Current evolutionary heory. Princeton: Princeton university Press.

Wilson, e. o. 1975. Sociobiology: he New Synthesis. Cambridge ma: Harvard university Press. Wilson , e. o. 1978. On Human Nature. Toronto: Bantam Books.

Referensi

Dokumen terkait

Sesuai Surat Tugas Nomor Nomor 11/ST/V/01/2017 tanggal 20 Januari 2017, BPK melaksanaan Pemeriksaan atas Laporan Keuangan Tahun 2016 pada Kementerian Riset, Teknologi, dan Pendidikan

In essence, trademark owners may not use their exclusive rights to stop sales or control subsequent marketing from a trademarked product or good after first sale had

Varietas “Green tiger”, “Green arrow”, “Golden hahnii”, dan “Hahnii cream” mempunyai bentuk sel yang sama yaitu hexagonal sempit dan memanjang, sedangkan varietas “Hahnii

Kesimpulan : Terdapat hubungan yang signifikan antara kadar prealbumin dengan status nutrisi pada anak sakit kritis di Rumah Sakit Haji Adam Malik Medan. Kunci : prealbumin,

Sebuah Tesis yang diajukan untuk memenuhi salah satu syarat memperoleh gelar Magister Pendidikan (M.Pd.) pada Program Studi Pendidikan Kebutuhan Khusus. © Yadi Heryadi 2014

Usulan Teknis dinyatakan memenuhi syarat (lulus) apabila mendapat nilai minimal 70 (tujuh puluh), peserta yang dinyatakan lulus akan dilanjutkan pada proses

A circle is a simple shape of Euclidean geometry that is the set of all points in a plane that are at a given distance from a given point, the centre.. The distance between any of

4 Pengembangan Bangunan Gedung Negara/BersejarahPengembangan Bangunan Gedung Negara dan Bersejara Kota Muara Teweh 1 paket 2017 19.286.000 14.195.000 4.330.675 5 Sarana dan